john locks
LOCKE'S
LIFE AND WORK
LOCKE'S
LIFE AND TIMES
John Locke
lived during a particularly turbulent period of English history and was
personally associated with some of its most dramatic episodes, despite
possessing a rather quiet and retiring character. He was born in Somerset in
1632, the son of a small landowner and attorney, also named John (1606-61), and
his wife Agnes (1597–1654). In spite of these relatively humble beginnings, he
received an excellent education, first at Westminster School and then at Christ
Church, Oxford. These advantages were made possible through connections that
his father had with people richer and more influential than himself. Patronage
of this sort was one of the few means available in seventeenth-century England
for people of little wealth to advance themselves, and Locke was to rely on it
for a good deal of his life, ultimately rising to positions of considerable
importance. Perhaps the most lasting legacy that Locke received from his
parents, however, was his strong Protestant faith, which was to exercise a very
large influence on his future intellectual development and political
allegiances.
After
receiving his B.A. degree at Oxford University in 1656, following a traditional
course of study in Arts, Locke retained his Studentship at Christ Church,
entitling him to rooms in college and a stipend - a position which he retained
until he was expelled at the direct instigation of Charles II (1630–85) in
1684, as a consequence of Locke's involvement with political groups opposed to
royal policies at the time. At Oxford, Locke was engaged not only in
philosophical and theological studies, but was also particularly interested in
medicine, and indeed in science quite generally (he became a Fellow of the
recently founded Royal Society in 1668). Locke's interest in medicine was
fostered by his association with the eminent physician Thomas Sydenham
(1624–89), and he was eventually to receive the medical degree of M.B. from
Oxford University in 1675. His knowledge of medicine was to stand him in good
stead when, after a chance meeting in 1666 with Lord Ashley (1621–83), then the
Chancellor of the Exchequer, he became Lord Ashley's medical adviser, taking up
residence in his London house in 1667 and staying there until 1675. Locke was
responsible for overseeing a serious liver operation on Lord Ashley in 1668,
from which the patient recovered, thereafter regarding Locke as one of his
closest friends and confidants.
Locke's
association with Lord Ashley – soon to become the first Earl of Shaftesbury
(1672) – was the most momentous development in his career. Shaftesbury's
influence at the court of Charles II was very great until the King dismissed him
in 1673, although he was briefly to return to public office in 1679. From this
time onwards English politics were greatly disturbed by the problem of the
succession to the throne, Charles II having no children and his brother and
heir, James II (1633–1707), being known for his strong allegiance to Roman
Catholicism. Whig politicians like Ashley and his circle, which included Locke
in a minor capacity, wanted a bill to be passed by Parliament excluding James
from the succession - a move very much opposed by Charles II and his court. At
this time royal power was still very considerable, and opposition like
Shaftesbury's extremely dangerous. Shaftesbury himself escaped to the
Netherlands in 1682 after a charge of treason had been levelled against him,
but died soon after his arrival, early in 1683.
By this
time Locke, who had been travelling abroad during 1675-9 but had not resumed
his membership of Shaftesbury's household upon his return, was still closely
associated with Shaftesbury's circle and hence in considerable personal danger
himself. Government spies kept a close watch on his activities, particularly
looking for any evidence of seditious writings. In the summer of 1683 matters
came to a head with the Rye House plot, when leading members of Shaftesbury's
circle – Algernon Sydney, Lord William Russell and the Earl of Essex – were
implicated in an attempt to kidnap Charles II and his brother and were all
three arrested for treason, two of them subsequently being executed. Locke,
though not directly involved in this conspiracy, was now even more under
suspicion, and escaped to the Netherlands in September 1683. From here he did
not return to England until 1689. Following the Revolutionary Settlement of
1688, which removed James II from the throne after a disastrous reign of three
years, the monarchy passed jointly to the Dutch Prince of Orange, William
(1650–1702), and his wife Mary (1662–94), who were James II's nephew and
daughter. With the reign of the Protestant William and Mary began the long
period of Whig ascendancy in English politics, a regime very much in tune with
Locke's own political and religious orientations.
During his
last years, from his return to England in 1689 to his death in 1704, Locke
enjoyed public esteem and royal favour, in addition to great intellectual fame
as the author of the Essay Concerning Human Understanding, which was published
late in 1689. He performed a number of official duties, notably as a
Commissioner of the Board of Trade, though his greatest desire was to pursue
his literary and intellectual interests, including a good deal of
correspondence. After some years of failing health, Locke died, aged 72, at the
Essex home of Sir Francis and Lady Masham, a wealthy family with whom he had
resided since 1692.
Locke never
married and had no children of his own, although he was fond of them and was
influential in promoting more humane and rational attitudes towards their
upbringing and education – never forgetting, it seems, the severe treatment he
had received at Westminster School. In character he was somewhat introverted
and hypochondriacal, but he by no means avoided company. He enjoyed good
conversation but was abstemious in his habits of eating and drinking. He was a
prolific correspondent and had a great many friends and acquaintances, on the
continent of Europe as well as in Britain and Ireland. If there was a
particular fault in his character, it was a slight tetchiness in response to
criticism of his writings, even when that criticism was intended to be
constructive. Though academic in his cast of mind, Locke was strongly moved by
his political and religious convictions - especially by his concern for liberty
and toleration - and had the good fortune to live at a time when there was no
great divide between the academic pursuit of philosophical interests and the
public discussion and application of political and religious principles. He
thus happily lived to see some of his most strongly held intellectual
convictions realised in public policy, partly as a consequence of his own
writings and involvement in public affairs.
THE
STRUCTURE OF THE ESSAY AND ITS PLACE IN LOCKE'S WORK
Locke's Essay Concerning Human Understanding,
which was first published in full in December 1689, was undoubtedly his
greatest intellectual achievement. He had been working on it off and on since
the early 1670s, but most intensively during his period of exile in the
Netherlands between 1683 and 1689. He continued to revise it after its first
appearance, supervising three further editions of it in his remaining years.
The fourth edition of 1700 accordingly represents his final view, and is the
version most closely studied today.
The Essay
is chiefly concerned with issues in what would today be called epistemology (or
the theory of knowledge), metaphysics, the philosophy of mind and the
philosophy of language. As its title implies, its purpose is to discover, from
an examination of the workings of the human mind, just what we are capable of
knowing and understanding about the universe we live in. Locke's answer is that
all the materials of our understanding come from our 'ideas' – both of
sensation and of reflection (that is, of 'outward' and ‘inward' experience,
respectively) - which are worked upon by our powers of reason to produce such
'real' knowledge as we can hope to attain. Beyond that, we have other sources
of belief – for instance, in testimony and in revelation – which may afford us
probability and hence warrant our assent, but do not entitle us to certainty.
Given these
concerns, we can readily understand the overall structure of the Essay, which
is divided into four books. Book I, Of Innate Notions', is devoted to an attack
on the advocates of innate ideas, who held that much of our knowledge is
independent of experience. In Book II, 'Of Ideas', Locke attempts to explain in
some detail how sensation and reflection can in fact provide all the
‘materials' of our understanding, even insofar as it embraces such relatively
abstruse ideas as those of substance, identity and causality, which many of
Locke's opponents took to be paradigmatically innate. In Book III, 'Of Words',
Locke presents his account of how language both helps and hinders us in the
communication of our ideas. Without such communication we could not hope to
achieve mutual understanding, given Locke's view of the origins of our ideas in
widely varying individual experience. Finally, in Book IV, 'Of Knowledge and
Opinion', Locke discusses the ways in which processes of reason, learning and
testimony operate upon our ideas to produce certain knowledge and probable
belief, and at the same time he tries to locate the proper boundary between the
province of reason and experience on the one hand and that of revelation and
faith on the other.
Locke's
view of our intellectual capacities is clearly a modest one. At the same time,
he held a strong personal faith in the truth of Christian religious principles,
which may seem to conflict with the mildly sceptical air of his epistemological
doctrines. In fact, he himself perceived no conflict here – unlike some of his
contemporary critics – though he did regard his modest view of our intellectual
capacities as providing a strong motive for religious toleration. Reason, he
thought, does not conflict with faith, but in questions of faith to which
reason supplies no answer it is both irrational and immoral to insist on
conformity of belief. We have it on record, indeed, that what originally
motivated Locke to pursue the inquiries of the Essay was precisely a concern to
settle how far reason and experience could take us in determining moral and
religious truths.
Locke's
concern with morality and religion, both intimately bound up with questions of
political philosophy in the seventeenth century, was one which dominated his
thinking throughout his intellectual and public career. His earliest works,
unpublished in his own lifetime, were the Two Tracts on Government (1660 and
1661) and the Essays on the Law of Nature (1664), both written in Latin but now
available in English translation. The position on issues of political liberty
and religious toleration that he adopted in those early works was, however,
considerably more conservative than the one that he later came to espouse,
following his association with Shaftesbury, and made famous in his Letter on
Toleration and Two Treatises of Government (both published anonymously in 1689,
the former in Latin and the latter in English). The Second Treatise explicitly
recognises the right of subjects to overthrow even a legitimately appointed
ruler who has abused his trust and tyrannises his people – a doctrine which
would almost certainly have led to Locke's being accused of sedition had the
manuscript been discovered by government spies. The First Treatise was an
extended attack upon an ultra-royalist tract written by Sir Robert Filmer (d.
1653), entitled Patriarcha (published 1680), in which the divine right of kings
was defended as proceeding from the dominion first granted by God to Adam.
Algernon Sydney (1622–83), one of the Rye House plot conspirators, had been
convicted of sedition partly on the strength of a manuscript he had written
attacking Filmer's work, so one can well understand Locke's secrecy and caution
in the years preceding his flight to the Netherlands.
In addition
to the works already mentioned, Locke published a good many other writings,
notably on religious and educational topics. Some Thoughts Concerning Education
(1693) was the product of advice he had provided in correspondence, over a
number of years, to his friends Edward and Mary Clarke concerning the
upbringing of their children. This work went into many editions, proving to be
very popular and influential with more enlightened parents for a long time to
come. Locke's interest in the intellectual development of children is also
plain to see in the Essay itself, where it has a direct relevance to his
empiricist principles of learning and concept-formation.
Locke's
explicitly religious writings include The Reasonableness of Christianity (1695)
and the learned and lengthy Paraphrase and Notes on the Epistles of St Paul
(published posthumously, 1705-7). He also wrote on economic and monetary issues
connected with his various involvements in public and political affairs. He
even found time to compose a critique of the theories of the French philosopher
Nicholas Malebranche (1638–1715, a contemporary developer of Cartesian
philosophy), entitled An Examination of P. Malebranche's Opinion of Seeing All
Things in God. Other items included in his collected Works, which have run to
many editions, are extensive replies to Edward Stillingfleet (1635–99), bishop
of Worcester, answering hostile criticisms raised by the latter against the
Essay, and a long piece entitled 'Of the Conduct of the Understanding', which
was originally intended for inclusion in a later edition of the Essay.
From this
brief survey of Locke's work, we can see that although his most important
writings were published in his fifties and sixties, during a comparatively
short interval beginning in his most momentous year of 1689, his thoughts were
the product of a very long period of gestation stretching back at least thirty
years before that. It is quite fair to say, however, that the Essay was the
cornerstone of all his intellectual activity, providing the epistemological and
methodological framework for all his other views and enterprises. And although
we are particularly fortunate in having a remarkably complete collection of
Locke's original manuscripts and letters as well as his many other
publications, it is on the Essay that his reputation as the greatest English
philosopher stands. Written in English at a time when English prose style was
at the peak of its vigour, and Latin had begun to wane as the language of
intellectual communication, it is both a literary and a philosophical
masterpiece, which can still be read today for pleasure as well as
enlightenment. Although in reading the Essay it is helpful to know something of
the historical and intellectual background to its composition, it is a
remarkable testimony to its durability and stature as a work of philosophy, as
well as to its appeal as a work of literature, that it can still be taken up
and studied with profit and pleasure, three hundred years after its first
appearance, by anyone susceptible to the intellectual curiosity that its pages
provoke.
Commentaires
Enregistrer un commentaire